Anticipatory Conditioning? [B. F.
Skinner]
Behaviorism as a superseded Theory.
These
days, for
the most part, the behaviorist school of psychology has been superseded
by the more cognitive schools of psychology and is currently relegated
to the background in psychological research. However, the behaviorist
school was the primary mover in psychological research since it was
inaugurated by John Watson in about 1920, and reached its peak in the
meticulous work of B. F. Skinner in the 1940s-80s. This research is
vast and still has much to tell us today if only we are able to see
past the ideas, that ignore internal cognitive processes, and try to
understand the research in terms that allow for internal cognitive
processes.
It
should also be noted, that although behaviorist ideas are no longer at
the forefront of academic acceptability, they are still having an
enormous impact on the average person in the street. Behaviorist ideas
have seeped into the general consciousness of people in today's
societies. This is so much so that behaviorist ideas are often taken to
be common sense.
But
often popular behaviorist ideas are a misunderstanding of
behaviorism, where the fact that all parties are being conditioned
is completely ignored. Although one individual is being punished, the
punisher is rewarded for punishing by
cessation of a target behavior or by the endorphins and dopermine
produced by anger and exercise. Parents are negatively reinforced to
put the baby in their bed because it causes the baby to stop crying.
The baby is reinforced to often cry at night.
These
populist behaviorist ideas have further been widely accepted by our
educational institutions, which seem only dimly aware of the newer
ideas in psychology and social psychology. Thus it seems any discussion
of learning must begin with some attempt to deal with behaviorist ideas
and find a way of perceiving behaviorist research from a different
perspective.
Operant conditioning.
B. F. Skinner and the other behaviorists have
tried to create a science of learning that is free of subjective
experience. To this end, they like to talk about only behavior and
environmental conditions. They ignore what is going on inside organisms
in favor of that which can be observed. They called this way of
studying or working operant conditioning. They have some idea that
anything which cannot be observed is not real. However, if pushed, most
will provide a subjective explanation of what they believe is happening.
The behaviorist explanation is, that behavior is
channeled by the association of pleasure and pain with other events.
They will explain some events are associated with pleasure and that
organisms try to replicate those events. Similarly, some events are
associated with pain and organisms try to escape from or avoid such
events. They believe that pleasure moves us forward and that pain holds
us back. This seems to make sense, unless we look clearly at what the
implications are for an organism. Are we just pleasure seeking, pain
avoiding organisms? A cursory glance at any human activity simply
denies that this is true.
Throwing
out the baby with the bath
water.
We have a choice; we can either say that
behaviorist
ideas are deficient and must be discarded or we can try to reinterpret
and modify their ideas in terms of more viable theories of learning
i.e.. Kelly's, Maslow's, Deci and Ryan's, Dweck's or Popper's. Thus we
can draw on the vast experiments performed by the behaviorists and see
how their theories work perceived in terms of Kelly's constructs or as
Popper's idea that organisms need to search for consistency in the
universe. This site chooses to do the latter. We do not have to throw
out the baby with the bath water.
Operant Conditioning?
Positive
Reinforcement?
This is the cornerstone
idea of the behaviorists. The behaviorists commandeered the word
reinforcement in order to avoid any implication of intervening (not
observable) events. Reinforcement was used previously to mean to make a
structure stronger, more durable and more resistant to change. The
behaviorist use it to mean to make a behavior stronger, more durable
and more resistant to change. This completely ignores the organism
performing the behavior and in particular its intentions. It's worth
noting that animal trainers have long realized that they have to give
rewards even if an animal does not perform the way the trainer wants.
Otherwise the relationship between the trainer and the animal will be
crushed. Behaviorists never took into account the need for
relationships and how they would affect outcomes.
Be that as it may, the behaviorists imply that
pleasure or as they put it "reinforcement" is associated with that
behavior which makes it likelier to re-occur. These behaviorists tend
to apply their ideas to all organisms. By this they could mean a human,
a rat or an insect. Skinner worked with what he called emitted
behaviors. These are behaviors performed by the organism, for whatever
reason, which the experimenter tries to make more likely to occur again
by reinforcing it. Reinforcement usually takes the form of some kind of
reward. For an animal the reward might be food. For a human it might be
praise. The reward is given to the organism within moments of
completing the required behavior. Not surprisingly the organism tends
to perform the behavior statistically more often than before.
Unfortunately for humans at home and in schools when positive
reinforcement is used it usually takes the form of conditional positive
reinforcement where the behavior is not emitted by the person and then
reinforced. Instead the person is told in advance that, if they do this
they will get a reward. This carries unpleasant side effects like
feeling controlled or manipulated.
Regardless, what is really happening in the
behaviorist
experiments? First of all such things as food or praise might be better
characterized as part of satisfying that creature's needs. Most
important here, however, is the point of view of the organism. How does
the organism see, understand or construe what is happening. The moment
we put ourselves in the organism's place, what is really happening
becomes quite clear. The organism is anticipating being rewarded with
food or praise or whatever if it performs the required behavior. This
is to say, it
has consciously or unconsciously formed a conjecture that this behavior
will be followed by something it wishes to happen. The organism is not
at the mercy of drives beyond its control. It chooses to do something
that it anticipates will cause something pleasant or satisfying to
occur. If the reward is not forthcoming obviously the likelihood of the
subject continuing to perform the activity will lessen with each lack
of reward. For more
on learning and positive reinforcement click here. Extrinsic rewards
work best when they most faithfully follow the behaviorist methodology
or when they are given randomly and unexpectedly so that unpleasant
associations do not occur.
Negative
Reinforcement?
Negative reinforcement is
nearly the same as positive reinforcement. The behavior of the organism
is still rewarded, and thus reinforced, but this is accomplished using
a negative stimulus. The organism is placed in a situation where it is
continually unpleasantly stimulated. The reward or reinforcement occurs
when the organism is released from the discomfort of the unpleasant
stimulation or even just by its reduction. Negative reinforcement
usually takes the form of some kind of escape from punishment. An
animal might be allowed to escape from an unpleasant environment, or a
human might escape or be allowed to seek relief from social
pressures. If cessation of punishment occurs within moments of
completing the required behavior, of course the organism tends to
perform the behavior statistically more often than before.
To
really understand why the behaviorist view is likely to be only
partially correct, we must again put ourselves in the position of the
organism. Surely the organism is anticipating being able to escape from
discomfiture if it performs a behavior. This is to say, that
more is happening than can be observed and the organism has formed a
conscious or unconscious conjecture that this behavior will be followed
by, being able to avoid something it does not wish to happen. For
instance the baby in the cartoon below wishes to escape the fear caused
by
being alone in the dark.
Organisms
are not at the mercy of automatic mechanisms that determine their
response but rather this response is mediated by anticipation. Thus
they choose to perform an action that they anticipate will allow them
to avoid something that is likely to be unpleasant.
For more on learning and negative reinforcement click here.
Positive punishment?
Positive aversion (punishment) could be
said to be the opposite of positive reinforcement in that it has as its
goal the reduction or extinction of a behavior. The idea is that pain,
discomfiture, or any unpleasantness (i.e. a negative stimulus) is
associated with a behavior. This is accomplished by following the
behavior with a negative stimulus. This, the behaviorists initially
believed would lead to the statistical reduction of the behavior and
its eventual extinction. Working with emitted behaviors the
experimenters tried to make some behavior less likely to occur again by
creating an aversion to it. Clearly the action or behavior was being
punished. The organism was punished within moments of completing the
behavior.
The behaviorists were most likely surprised to
find that
while the organism tended to perform the behavior statistically less
often than before, that this had even less lasting effect than did
positive reinforcement. Not only that, but they discovered that when
previously reinforced behaviors were subjected to strenuous and
continuous negative stimuli, the behaviors became less regular, but the
organism eventually had what could only be interpreted as a nervous
breakdown. In other words they were no longer able to be guided
properly by whatever intellect they had.
These problems with punishment, or the creating of
an aversion, becomes clearer if we are willing to accept that something
else is going on, and not just a reflexive response. Organisms process
the information coming in, and anticipate being punished if they
perform that behavior. The organisms consciously or unconsciously form
a conjecture that the behavior will be followed by something they wish
to avoid happening. Again the organisms are deciding what to do. They
are choosing not to do something that they anticipate will enable them
to avoid unpleasantness. However if the behavior is also rewarding they
may decide to risk the punishment (unpleasantness) in order to get the
reward. Too much of this reward/punishment conflict causes all
creatures including humans to become very disturbed. Of course it is
possible to create real aversions both in humans and animals but these
are more like mental disorders. We call them phobias and they are understood to
be irrational. Punishment also has the unfortunate side effect of
tuning the subjects into punishers as that is the behavior that is
being modeled for them. For more on learning and positive aversion
click here.
Negative punishment?
The idea with
negative punishment
is still to make a behavior of an organism less likely to occur, but
this is accomplished using the absence of pleasure rather than
punishment as such. The organism is placed in a situation where it is
continually pleasantly stimulated. The organism is then deprived of
this pleasure during or just following the behavior that is to be
reduced or eliminated. Here the organism is not trying to escape
punishment but rather trying to maintain the situation of continual
reward. This kind of absence of reward is often used by parents in
punishing children as in the idea of being grounded (not allowed the
pleasure of going out.), having one's cellphone withheld or not being
allowed to watch T. V. or deprived of ice cream. If
pleasure ceases
during or within moments of the completion of a behavior of course the
organism tends to perform the behavior statistically less often than
before.
But what is the point of view of the organism? How
and why does the organism react to what is happening? Only by putting
ourselves in the organism's position can we begin to see past the
behaviorist view of what is happening. Again the organism is
anticipating being deprived of food or loosing the privilege of going
out if it performs the behavior. This is to say, it has consciously or
unconsciously formed a conjecture that this behavior will be followed
by the loss of something it enjoys. Again the organism is not at the
mercy of drives beyond its control. It chooses not to do something that
it anticipates will allow it to avoid the loss of something pleasant.
However, if the behavior is also rewarding the organism may decide to
risk the loss of pleasantness in order to get something more pleasant.
This kind of punishment is obviously less dangerous in that it is less
likely to produce a nervous breakdown, but is clearly not very
effective. To the organism it now seems that it is being asked to
choose between two pleasures or two rewards and can obviously choose
the one it prefers. For more on learning and negative aversion click
here.
Interest
and Disinterest.
What the behaviorists call the environmental
conditioning of
learning is actually the development of interest and
disinterest on the one hand and habits on the other. All
creatures, far from being conditioned to learn, learn instead because
they anticipate. They anticipate learning will be followed by the
satisfaction of needs or be accompanied by pleasure. All creatures,
(organisms) will choose to learn because they anticipate its
desirability. Creatures far from being conditioned not to learn,
rather do not learn because they anticipate that learning will be
accompanied by failure in the satisfaction of needs or be followed by
displeasure. Creatures, organisms if you will, choose not to learn
because they anticipate its undesirability. The development of
interests and disinterests is the conscious part of dealing with
rewards and punishments or pleasure and pain. With interest and
disinterest the conscious brain is understood to intervene and make
logical choices. The behaviorists simply ignored this because it was
subjective experience and as such could not be tested.
Habits
and superstitions.
Habits in many ways are what behaviorists were
studying. They are actions that are rewarded usually without intension
or by accident. They are much more like automatic reflexes than other
behaviors because we do not take notice of the rewards involved and our
conscious brains do not intervene to make choices. Indeed the only
conscious intervention in habits are those performed after a habit is
formed in an effort to break the habit.
Superstitions on the other hand form the same way
as habits, but are to do with beliefs rather than just performing
actions, and are usually held in contradiction of logic and common
sense. While
humans can react
rationally to form expectations and anticipate events, we do not always
do so. Our brains and the brains of other creatures are pattern seeking
devices that seek to find ways of controlling events.
Scientifically
we
understand that we can control events through the process of causation.
If we can see a relation between action A and event B where we
understand A causes B we can implement event B by performing action A.
The behaviorists of course ignore all this subjective intervention, and
instead of invoking causality and anticipation, simply rely on
associations of time and place.
Causation
and superstition.
Our
brains seek causation, and
sometimes we seem to find it even though it isn't there. When this occurs
we cease real learning and become superstitious. We find ourselves
performing actions to cause or avoid events where there is no causal
relationship. Two things happen in close proximity of time and space
and we react as if there is a causal effect between them, even when we
understand on a rational level that there is no causal relation. This
mechanism in our brains that seeks causality is usually fairly good at
finding causality, but sometimes as in this case it leads us astray.
Coincidence
gambling and sport.
The
real relationship in these cases is
that of coincidence. We tend to ignore this however, and rationalize
these actions as rituals we perform for luck. Some of these are curious
cultural leftovers from primitive times such as unlucky 13, black cats,
knocking on wood and spilt salt, which are all easily recognized as
socially pervasive superstitions.
However,
most of what should be
called
superstition is personal, specific to individual persons, and has
become formed out of coincidences that have occurred in that person's
life. Gamblers and sports people in particular are very prone to these
kinds of false, scientifically ridiculous beliefs. In his book
"Don't Believe Everything You Think" Thomas Kida provides the
following examples:
"Wade
Boggs was one of the most proficient hitters in the history of
baseball. He won the batting title five times and had a lifetime
batting average of .363. He is also highly superstitious. Early on in
his career he formed the belief that he could hit better after eating
chicken. For that reason, he ate chicken almost every day for twenty
years when he played baseball. He is not alone in his superstitious
behavior. Wayne Gretzky, the great hockey star, always tucked in the
right side of his jersey behind the hip pads. Jim Kelly, the Buffalo
Bills quarterback, forced himself to vomit before every game. Bjorn
Borg did not shave after he began to play in a major tennis tournament.
Bill Parcells would buy coffee from two different coffee shops before
every game when he coached the New York Giants.
Superstition in
Pigeons.
Perhaps
Skinner's most important contribution in
understanding how learning works is his paper "Superstition in the
Pigeon". This paper convincingly demonstrated that coincidence develops
superstitious behavior. Again in his book
"Don't Believe Everything You Think" Thomas Kida explains the
experiment behind Skinner's paper:
"Skinner
put pigeons into separate cages and had a prize (food) dropped
periodically (remarkably similar to slot machine payouts!) After just
a few minutes, each bird exhibited a different bizarre behavior.
Some
bobbed their heads up and down, others walked in circles, while still
others thrust their heads into different places in the cage. It turned
out that the birds repeated the behaviors they performed just
prior to receiving the food. Since they were doing different things
just before the food arrived, they developed different rituals. In
essence, the pigeons' behavior was the result of coincidence based on
what they were doing when the food appeared. So it is with many human
superstitions."
Superstition
and persistence.
The
above experiment is easy to repeat, and it is almost impossible to
imagine another explanation for the strange behaviors of the birds. In
other words all the variables are accounted for and nothing needs to be
controlled for. If the birds are not fed they die. If plenty of food is
placed in each of the cages the birds are not motivated. More food
coming into the cage is unimportant to the birds if they are well fed.
The birds feel the necessity to try and control their feed drop because
it is not quite enough and the birds are hungry.
Basically the pigeons
want some thing to happen (the food to drop down). It seems to happen
when they do something. So they try doing that thing again. Of course
it does not work but the birds do not stop trying. The birds try again
and again. Suddenly it does seem to work. The pigeons try again and it
does not work. But now the pigeons are much
more committed to their
ritual. It has worked on at least two occasions. The pigeons become
persistent in their actions. They perform the actions over and over
again until eventually it does seem to work again.
Superstition
and intermittent reward.
In
the parlance of the behaviorists, these pigeons are being reinforced in
their actions. This kind of reinforcement is called intermittent
reinforcement. It is intermittent because the pigeons are not always
rewarded. The birds are only rewarded sometimes, but this has been
examined at length in behaviorist literature, and found to be very
effective in motivating.
The development of human
superstitious ritual.
How does this work in the
world of human superstition? Let us consider a gambler. Suppose this
gambler blows on his dice just before he roles them. Suppose he wins.
Next time he blows on the dice and loses. Does he give up blowing on
the dice? No. He blows on the dice and roles again. perhaps he loses
again. Perhaps he blows and loses three times in a row. Does he give
up? Probably not. Perhaps he blows and wins. Now the desire to blow on
the dice is greater. It has worked twice. (Never mind all the times it
didn't work.) Perhaps if he blew on the dice twenty times in a row and
lost each time he would stop blowing on the dice. But the likelihood of
losing twenty times in a row is small. In this way seemingly the human
also gets intermittently rewarded for blowing on the dice. What
happens if it is pointed out to the person that there cannot be a
causal connection between the blowing on the dice and whether
he wins or not? Scientifically this is a given, so the person may be
able to be convinced that there is no causal relationship. Does this
mean he will stop blowing on the dice? Not likely. Even though people
fully understand it is irrational they will usually still persist in
performing superstitious ritual.
Logic
and intermittent reward.
The point is that the
more intermittent the reward the longer this superstitious behavior
will persist. This makes perfect common sense as who or what would not
continue to try if they believed that the reward would only come
sometimes. It is worth noting that organisms conditioned in this way
many times may not be able to stop performing the action. It
may
become
a compulsion.
Justification
and rationalization.
If
asked why they are continuing to perform such an irrational action
superstitious people may try to rationalize or justify the action. In
the case of the man blowing on the dice he may say that doing it hurts
no one. He may suggest that there are possibilities beyond those
understood in science. He may say that an action, no matter how
illogical or how unlikely of being effective, is worth doing
if the reward is high enough and the
effort required is small.
Humans are not completely rational.
So there it is. We humans are not completely
rational. We can be
rational, but even the most rigorous scientific minds can be drawn into
performing irrational actions akin to magic. This kind of superstitious
behavior is so prevalent in human behavior that we are hardly aware
that we are indulging in it. All of us have little behavioral quirks
where we do things that make no rational sense.
All of these behaviors
can be traced back to what we were doing when something good or bad
happened. If something bad happened we try to never again perform that
action. If something good happened we will try to perform the action
again, as often as is possible. There is in these cases no causal
relation, we are aware that there is no causation, but we perform the
action anyway. For instance, although most people will say they do not
believe in horoscopes, they will still follow the advice of such
writings in magazines. The extreme case of this is of course obsessive
compulsive disorder.
Changing anticipation
& expectation.
Elsewhere in this site it is explained that
extrinsic reward is
difficult to make work, because its motivational power tends to
evaporate when it is removed. (This is particularly true as extrinsic
reward is suddenly transformed into an extrinsic punishment when it is removed.) However,
some behaviors persist after a reward or
punishment have been withdrawn. This is of course not incompatible with
the idea that expectation or anticipation will continue after a reward
has been withdrawn. The conjectures that we form about reality are
dogmatic so a single event where a reward or punishment is not
forthcoming does not invalidate the conjecture, and thus the
expectation or anticipation does not weaken immediately. Of course, it
is obvious, that if the reward or punishment continues not to be
forthcoming over a long period, then our conjecture must be and is
revised to fit the events and the expectation or anticipation gradually
fades.
Behaviors
also sometimes do not fade despite the fact that a reward or punishment
is not forthcoming. Expectation and anticipation can explain this far
better than the behaviorist associations ever could. The explanation is
simple. The behavior continues but the expectation or anticipation
change. A new conjecture is formed involving a different reward,
probably a different type of reward. In other words the reward has been
withdrawn, but is replaced by another reward, one probably not taken
into account by the experimenter. With humans, we see evidence of this
around us all the time. We start off doing something for one reason
(for one type of reward) and end up doing the same thing for quite a
different reason (for another type of reward).
Rewards and punishments in
clusters.
Any behavior a
living
organism may perform will involve many conjectures or many
anticipations of pleasure and pain. Many of our needs, for instance,
can be satisfied by a single action. The person who does good work in
the community may satisfy every level on Maslow's hierarchy. The
behavior may put food in his mouth, it may make him feel safer. It may
help him to gain love and friendship and it will certainly increase the
regard in which he is held by others. On top of that, many meta needs
may be satisfied such as the need for creation and the need for
justice. These satisfactions can all be considered rewards. Then also,
learning and accomplishment can also be considered rewards. In the
final analysis all these rewards and possible punishments must be
considered in the expectations of someone doing good community works.
Almost any action taken by an individual can be examined in this way
and it will be found the activity is always performed for many
different reasons.
Needs necessitate anticipation.
Our needs determine
what we will try to
anticipate. But if needs
provide the expectations of reward, what provides the punishments? The
expectations of punishment can be found in the same needs etc. For it
is in the successful satisfaction of these needs that they are rewards,
and in their deprivation, they are punishments. In making a choice as
to whether to perform a behavior, an organism must take into account
many anticipated rewards and punishments. It must decide if the
pleasures it anticipates are worth the pain it also anticipates. Of
course this is probably never done consciously. Intrinsic and extrinsic rewards.
It has been found,
however, that if we start off performing an action for an intrinsic
reward and are the provided with an extrinsic reward the intrinsic
reward will lose its ability to motivate. Unfortunately the reverse is
not true. If you start off performing an action for an extrinsic reward
this makes it difficult to graduate to being motivated intrinsically.
For more on this check out the pages on motivation and creativity.
Skinner boxes and the need
to learn.
The Skinner box was invented
by B. F. Skinner to enable small animals and birds to have some control
over whether they get fed or not. A Skinner box is basically a cage
with a leaver, that when pressed, causes a pellet of food to drop into
a dispenser in the cage. In his book
"The
Upside of Irrationality" Dan
Ariely describes an experiment performed by psychologist Glen Jensen.
In his experiment Jensen places a hungry rat in a Skinner box. The rat
accidentally pushes the leaver and learns that when it pushes the
leaver, a pellet of food drops into the food dispenser which enables it
to eat. The rat then engages in a lot of lever pushing activity. As
soon as the rat seemed to get the hang of this Jensen turned off the
light in the box and simultaneously deactivated the ability of the
lever to dispense pellets of food. The rat of course continues to push
the lever but no pellets are forthcoming. Eventually Jensen turns the
light back on and reengages the lever's power to dispense pellets.
After having experienced this several times the rats learn that the
lever only works when the light is on. Jensen then turns the light off
in the box and places a cup filled with food pellets into the box. The
rat eventually finds this and begins to eat. Then Jensen turns the
light back on. Contra to what might be expected, out of hundreds of
rats tested, all them eventually returned to pushing the lever. Dan
Ariely in "The Upside of Irrationality" tells us the following:
"Jensen
discovered (and many subsequent experiments confirmed) that many
animals - including fish, gerbils, rats, mice, monkeys and chimpanzees
-
tend to prefer a longer, more indirect route to food than a shorter,
more direct one. That is, as long as fish, birds, gerbils, rats, mice,
monkeys, and chimpanzees don't have to work too hard they frequently [seem
to] prefer to earn their food." Contrafreeloading.
However, Jensen's
theory about why this behavior occurs in the rats is what he
calls 'Contrafreeloading'. He proposes that the reason the rats go back
to lever pressing, despite the free food available in the cup, is
because they prefer to work for food, rather than get it for free. Here's the thing. This is an interesting experiment but it does not prove what Ariely and Jensen suggests above.
Saving
against tomorrow.
There can, however, be other reasons why
animals might prefer to return to lever pressing instead of gobbling up
the free food. One possible reason is that the animals may be motivated
to keep their free food as a kind of secure storage against a future
where the lever is not working, as with the lights off condition. The
rat may feel more secure knowing the storage is there. In this case the
rat can feed itself and still have plenty in dire times.
Learning as finding limits through iteration.
But there is
another possibility, and a more compelling one, that has to do with
learning. From an evolutionary point of view it is more important for
an animal to learn how to provide food for itself, than it is to to
just eat. It may be possible then, that the act of pressing the lever
by an animal, can be construed by that animal as act of learning. Now
you might be temped to say, the rat is not learning, as he has already
learned well that the lever pushing produces food when the lights are
on. But this is a misunderstanding of how learning takes place.
Limits and iteration.
Learning can be seen as a process of
finding the limits within which a principle works. Thus learning is the
testing of hypotheses to find the conditions within which those
hypotheses are not valid. So the question is this; when a rat presses
the lever, is that mere repetition of an action it has learned, or is
it a variation of past actions used experimentally? Is it an action
testing an hypothesis about how to obtain food in the future? If each
action the animal performs is a unique effort to test an hypothesis,
the action is not simple repetition, but rather an iteration of
previous actions meant to test the hypothesis under slightly different
conditions.
In
the case of the rat, or any other creature provided with an
opportunity to choose between free food and pressing a lever to obtain
food, the variations in self performance they could be testing are
infinite. What might make a difference, as to whether pressing a lever
causes food a pellet to drop down? Well the amount of pressure the
animal places on the lever will obviously make a difference. Perhaps
the speed at which the lever is pressed could make a difference. Maybe
how the animal stands or where it stands when it pushes the lever will
make a difference. Maybe how far the lever is pushed down will make a
difference. Not only all that but pressing the leaver may also be
considered an experiment to discover whether the the leaver pressing
will still produce a food pallet. In other words it may be a way of
ensuring that the creature is still able to control his food supply and
not be totally dependent on humans for its nourishment. The point is
there may be many limits, and the animal to be
secure about its future ability to procure food for itself, must learn
as many and as much as it can.
This
is a profoundly important principle of learning. Humans, animals,
organisms, all never truly just repeat their actions. Rather we are
continually testing hypotheses, continually learning something new,
continually refining our actions to be closer and closer to a universal
truth.
For more information about iteration and how it works as part of
learning, click here to go to
the iteration page.
The environment and life
long learning.
Behaviorists are so
concerned with getting
something or someone to
behave in a particular way that they seem oblivious to the idea that
controlling others might not be a good thing. It is one thing to
believe, that the associations formed in what they call reinforcement
mean we could control the actions and the direction of interest taken
by
others, but it is another thing to believe that this would be good for
society and therefore morally acceptable. Manipulation of people has
become such a part of western society that we have become blind to the
fact that such control is immoral and unproductive. This is especially
true when it comes to learning. As science delves further and further
into motivation and how the brain works it is becoming clearer that
learning should be in the hands of each individual learner and not some
other controlling person. Many educational theorists now agree that the
productive direction for the study of learning is to discover how we
can direct ourselves to become more interested in many and various
things and how we can successfully avoid becoming disinterested in
anything. In other words, if we are to structure an environment to
facilitate learning, it should an environment that engenders interest
in us for anything and everything and not conveniently herd us in a
particular direction. If we can do this we will find ourselves living
in a world where most people are occupied by learning throughout the
lives.
|